Untold Stories – Church and His System

WARNING

This article was translated from Chinese by ChatGPT and may contain some errors.

As a functional programming enthusiast, you must know Church and his λ\lambda calculus. If you have studied recursion theory, you may also know about λ\lambda definability, various properties of λ\lambda calculus (Church-Rosser theorem, fixed point theorem…), and how they are combined to give an undecidable proof of β\beta equivalence.

Of course, you may not know what these words are talking about, and thats okay. If you have studied a little bit of computer science, you must know about the Turing Machine. Some people regard Turing and his paper as the origin of computer science, but in fact, Church and his λ\lambda calculus are earlier and more elegant1. The story we are going to tell today is actually one of the origins of theoretical computer science.

Few people know why Church invented λ\lambda calculus at that time, and what is different between the system he invented at that time and the λ\lambda calculus we know now. In fact, Churchs system is much more complicated than todays λ\lambda calculus. Why was Churchs system forgotten, and todays λ\lambda calculus has become the cornerstone of computer science?

This is a very interesting story. I shared this story with my classmates in the SICP course in 20232, and now, I think it should be written down to let more people know about this history.

NOTE

This article has some technical details, but the important thing is the story. If you dont understand, you can skip it, it wont affect the understanding of the story. However, I suggest at least understanding the content of the first section, so you know what Church is roughly doing.

Formal Systems

The system that Church published in 19323 is now called a formal system. Simply put, a formal system has three elements:

  • Syntax - A set of symbols and rules to describe legal expressions (formula). The syntax here is no different from the syntax of a programming language, they both specify what the expressions in this system look like.
  • A set of axioms - A set of expressions that are considered true. These axioms are the foundation of the system, and other theorems are derived from these axioms.
  • Inference rules - A set of rules used to derive new theorems from known axioms and theorems.

I can propose an extremely simple formal system (denoted as PP):

  • Syntax - Strings composed of aa and bb. Such as aa, aaaa, abab, baba, etc.
  • Axioms - aa, bb
  • Inference rules
    • (I.) If xx is a theorem, then axaaxa and bxbbxb are also theorems.

All the theorems of this system are the so-called palindromes. For example, abaaba is a theorem, and its derivation process (we call it proof) is:

  • bb (Axiom)
  • abaaba (I.)

In logic, abaaba is a theorem of system PP can be written as PabaP \vdash aba. Here \vdash means derives.

Conversely, abab is not a theorem because we cannot derive it through the inference rules. This can be written as PabP \nvdash ab.

The axioms, theorems, and proofs mentioned here are all terms of formal systems. They have precise mathematical meanings. For example, here, axioms are aa and bb, theorems are palindromes, and proofs are sequences of strings that satisfy the inference rules. However, obviously, we have been receiving mathematical education from a young age, and axioms, theorems, and proofs have natural language meanings. Please allow me to take some time to explain their relationship.

The axiom in natural language, we will represent it as axiom below, and the axiom in the formal system, we represent it as axiom. We do similar treatment for other concepts.

We have learned various theorems from a young age, such as 1+1=21 + 1 = 2. These theorems were mostly proven before modern logic was established. Naturally, before logic, there were concepts such as proof and theorem. This mathematics described and constructed through natural language, we mostly consider it to be existing and correct.

And the theorem in the formal system, as we have said, is a strict mathematical object. We know its properties, we know how it is derived from axioms. This derivation process can be verified by a computer. In short, these mathematical objects are clear and strict. And the mathematics of natural language, at least does not have such strictness. For example, can you imagine a program that can easily verify all the proofs in a randomly selected mathematics textbook?

So in my opinion, the primary goal of the formal system is to solidify the mathematics of natural language with strict mathematical objects. Solidify, to express it in a more academic term, is called formalize.

The mathematics described by natural language and the mathematics described by the formal system are like algorithms and programs. An algorithm is a non-formal program, and a program is a formalized algorithm.

Formalizing mathematical proofs in natural language with formal systems is a very difficult problem. To solve this problem, we need more complex and troublesome formal systems. So, what kind of formal system should we choose?

For this difficult problem, most mathematicians believe that another discipline developed in the second half of the 19th centuryset theoryis the answer. Most mathematical objects can be described by set theory, and set theory can be described by formal systems. Principia Mathematica published by Russell from 1910 to 1913, and Zermelo-Fraenkel set theory (1908, 1922), are practices of this scheme. ZF set theory has basically become the foundation of modern mathematics.

Churchs System

In the 1920s, Church tried to provide a formal system using a non-set theory method. In his 1932 paper, Church said that he felt that both Russells Principia Mathematica and ZF set theory had adopted unnatural methods to deal with the famous Russells Paradox.

His method is to restrict the use of the law of excluded middle. Technically speaking, I personally feel that his method is even more unnatural, so that I find it difficult to give a clear explanation within the scope of this article. In short, he designed a formal system with 37 (yes, you read that right, just 37) axioms and 5 inference rules. These 5 inference rules led to modern λ\lambda calculus. This system was given in A Set of Postulates for the Foundation of Logic published in 1932.

In Churchs system, there are indeed no sets or classes in the syntax, which are composed of these symbols:

  1. Undefined terms. We are now ready to set down a list of the undefined terms of our formal logic. They are as follows:
    {}(), λ[], Π, Σ, &, , ι, A \{\}(),\ \lambda[],\ \Pi,\ \Sigma,\ \&, \ \sim, \ \iota, \ A

Among them, {}()\{\}() represents the action (apply, commonly known as function call) in modern λ\lambda calculus, λ[ ]\lambda [\ ] is naturally λ\lambda abstraction, Π\Pi is a more complex syntax, Π(P,Q)\Pi(P, Q) is roughly x.(P(x)Q(x))\forall x. (P(x) \to Q(x))4, Σ\Sigma is existence, &\& is logical and, \sim is logical not, ι\iota is similar to the μ\mu operator in recursive functions, ι(F)\iota(F) refers to the xx that {F}(x)\{F\}(x) holds. As for AA, this symbol is particularly abstract, and will not be discussed here.

Afterwards, Church defined some syntactic sugar, or macros. For example, he defined VV, which is \lor in modern logic, with the following definition:

V(P,Q).P.Q V(P, Q) \equiv \sim . \sim P . \sim Q

Expressed in todays symbols, it would be:

PQ¬(¬P¬Q) P \lor Q \equiv \neg (\neg P \land \neg Q)

Its worth mentioning that Church used the dot notation popular at the time and adopted by Russell to represent logical operations. Simply put, the dot determines the priority, which can reduce the use of parentheses. For example, .P.Q\sim . \sim P . \sim Q is a shorthand for (PQ)\sim (\sim P \land \sim Q). However, as far as I know, the dot symbol in Principia Mathematica does not seem to allow this usage, and this proposition in PM should be (P.Q)\sim (\sim P . \sim Q). (Of course, this could be my misunderstanding, I referred to The Notation in Principia Mathematica).

In addition, Church also defined the implication symbol \supset as a macro.

In summary, this is roughly the syntax of Churchs system. His 37 axioms are more complex. The 15th one might be easier to understand:

15. pqpqq \text{15.}\ pq \supset_{pq} q

This refers to pqqp \land q \to q. But most of the axioms are difficult to understand. For example, the first one:

1. Σ(φ)φΠ(φ,φ) \text{1.}\ \Sigma(\varphi) \supset_{\varphi} \Pi(\varphi, \varphi)

Π(φ,φ)\Pi(\varphi, \varphi) should hold without any premise (understood as x.(φ(x)φ(x))\forall x. (\varphi(x) \to \varphi(x))), but due to Churchs restrictions, Σ(φ)\Sigma(\varphi) must be ensured here.

Compared to the 37 incomprehensible axioms, his 5 inference rules seem very simple to us today. These 5 rules are quite similar to modern λ\lambda calculus. These 5 rules (with some of my rephrasing, but no difference from Churchs original text) are:

I. In a true formula JJ, if

  • All appearances of xx in JJ are bound appearances
  • yy does not appear freely in JJ,

Then, in JJ, the result KK of replacing xx with yy (denoted as Syx J\text{S}_{y}^{x}\ J) is also a true formula.

II. If

  • (λx.M)N(\lambda x. M) N is a sub-formula of true formula JJ
  • xx does not appear bound in MM
  • xx appears freely in MM (*)
  • xx does not appear freely in NN

Then, in JJ, the result KK of replacing a specific (λx.M)N(\lambda x. M) N with SNx M\text{S}_{N}^{x}\ M is also a true formula.

III. If

  • SNx M\text{S}_{N}^{x}\ M is a sub-formula of true formula JJ
  • xx does not appear bound in MM
  • xx appears freely in MM (*)
  • xx does not appear freely in NN

Then, in JJ, the result KK of replacing a specific SNx M\text{S}_{N}^{x}\ M with (λx.M)N(\lambda x. M) N is also a true formula.

IV. If F(A)F(A), then Σ(F)\Sigma(F).

V. If Π(F,G)\Pi(F, G), and F(A)F(A), then G(A)G(A).

These 5 rules, IV. and V. are similar to the existential quantifier introduction and modus ponens of first-order logic. The highlights are I., II. and III.:

  • I. is α\alpha equivalence
  • II. is one direction of β\beta equivalence, which can be regarded as β\beta reduction
  • III. is the other direction of β\beta equivalence, which can be regarded as β\beta abstraction

These three rules constitute the core of modern λ\lambda calculus. It is worth mentioning the rule marked with (*), which is not in the modern λ\lambda calculus. We will not discuss this matter for now, if you are interested, you can think about it yourself.

Kleene and λ\lambda Definability

I dont know how much you understand about these messy symbols above. If you showed it to me a few years ago, I would definitely be confused. Moreover, Churchs system has 37 axioms, and its overwhelming to think about proving in this system. Compared with ZF set theory, Churchs system is obviously overly complicated. Moreover, his approach of directly bypassing first-order logic adds some difficulty to learning.

Fortunately, Church had a student named Kleene.

Kleene came to Princeton University to read Churchs doctorate when he graduated from undergraduate at the age of 22 in 1931. Amazingly, he received his doctorate in 1934 at the age of 25. I have to exclaim that he is truly a genius, super genius 5!

In the fall semester of 1931, Church told Kleene and other students about his new inventionthat is, the system we mentioned above. From Kleenes recollection, Church had the idea of β\beta reduction at that time. What is β\beta reduction? Simply put, it is to regard (λx.M)N(\lambda x. M) N as a function call and replace it with SNxM\text{S}_{N}^{x} M. In other words, it is to derive a formula in his system using axiom II..

Importantly, this derivation can be seen as a calculation. If given a λ\lambda term aa, any number of β\beta reductions are performed to get bb, this can be seen as the calculation of λ\lambda calculus. In fact, this calculation also defines a relationship, aβba \rightarrow_{\beta} b, which means that aa can be obtained through β\beta reduction to bb.

Church also mentioned in his lecture at that time that he had found a way to define positive integers in his system, that is, the Church numbers we talk about today. 1,2,31, 2, 3 are defined as:

1(λf.λx.fx)2(λf.λx.f(fx))3(λf.λx.f(f(fx))) \mathsf{1} \equiv (\lambda f. \lambda x. f x) \\ \mathsf{2} \equiv (\lambda f. \lambda x. f (f x)) \\ \mathsf{3} \equiv(\lambda f. \lambda x. f (f (f x)))

Combined with the idea of aβba \to_{\beta} b above, Church found that some functions can be represented by λ\lambda terms, such as the successor function S(n)=n+1S(n) = n + 1, which can be represented by λ\lambda terms as:

Sλn.λf.λx.f(nfx) \mathsf{S} \equiv \lambda n. \lambda f. \lambda x. f (n f x)

It has the property S 1β2\mathsf{S}\ \mathsf{1} \to_{\beta} \mathsf{2}, more generally, Church proposed the concept of λ\lambda definability. His idea is that if a function ff can be represented by a λ\lambda term, then ff is λ\lambda definable.

Formally speaking, for a (partial) function ff, if there exists a λ\lambda term F\mathsf{F}, for natural numbers nn in the domain of ff, there is

F nβf(n) \mathsf{F}\ \mathsf{n} \to_{\beta} \mathsf{f(n)}

Then ff is λ\lambda definable. The above f(n)\mathsf{f(n)} refers to the Church number corresponding to f(n)f(n) (a natural number).

Church discovered that not only the successor function, but also the addition function f(x,y)=x+yf(x, y) = x + y is λ\lambda definable. However, Church did not know whether the predecessor function (P(n)=n1P(n) = n - 1) is λ\lambda definable. Of course, his system allows him to cheat, and he can get the predecessor function without λ\lambda definability. His definition is as follows:

λr.ιx.(S x=r) \lambda r. \iota x. (\mathsf{S}\ x = r)

The definition of this ι\iota was seen in the previous section, simply put, Church defines the predecessor of rr through the xx that satisfies S x=r\mathsf{S}\ x = r.

In early 1932, Church asked Kleene to try to prove the axioms of natural numbers (Peano Axioms) in his system. Kleene found that there must be a predecessor function here, and he was not particularly satisfied with Churchs cheating, so he began to study whether the predecessor function is λ\lambda definable.

In Kleenes recollection (see [Kleene 1981]), he initially wanted to change the definition of natural numbers a bit, but Church still wanted to use his Church numbers. So, he racked his brains to think about how to give a predecessor function. Finally, at the end of January or the beginning of February 1932, Kleene suddenly thought of a way to solve the problem of λ\lambda defining the predecessor function while at the dentists office. Then, Kleene gave a λ\lambda term that λ\lambda defined the predecessor function. I wont show the specific definition here, interested students can think about it themselves.

When Kleene told Church about his invention, Church said that he was about to give up:

When I brought this result to Church, he told me that he had just about convinced himself that there is no λ\lambda-definition of the predecessor function.

A function originally thought to be undefinable by λ\lambda was proven to be definable by Kleene. Kleene and Church began to ponder a new question:

What kind of function is λ\lambda definable?

To this question, 90 years later today, we blurt out: A function ff is λ\lambda definable if and only if ff is computable.

At that time, Kleenes main job was to prove some mathematical propositions in Churchs system. His side job was to study λ\lambda definability. He found that almost all intuitively computable natural number functions are λ\lambda definable. In 1933, Gödel came to Princeton. In 1934, he reported a method for defining recursive functions, which is now the so-called Herbrand-Gödel computable function. Kleene saw this report and realized that this method was related to his λ\lambda definability.

Eventually, in the papers published by Kleene and Church in 1935-36, a series of problems were proven:

  • β\approx_{\beta}, that is, β\beta equivalence, is λ\lambda undefinable
  • λ\lambda definable functions and Gödel computable functions are equivalent

The rest of the story is all too familiar. Turing published his paper in 1936, proposed the Turing Machine, and proved that the Turing Machine and Churchs λ\lambda calculus are equivalent. Theoretical computer science was born in this way.

Unfortunately, many people at the time felt that λ\lambda calculus was not very mathematical, so Kleenes subsequent great work was all based on his defined μ\mu-recursive functions; and when it comes to computing models, everyone prefers Turing machines.

How Churchs system was forgotten

The study of λ\lambda definability opened the door to modern computer science, but what about Churchs system?

Kleene, in his memoirs, said somewhat playfully:

This paper contains Gödels celebrated proof of the existence of undecidable sentences in formal systems embodying the usual elementary number theory, and his second theorem on the impossibility of a proof of the consistency of such a system within the system itself. Churchs immediate reaction was that his formal system, about which I am going to say more, is sufficiently different from the systems Gödel dealt with that Gödels second theorem might not apply to it (see Church 1933 top p. 843). Indeed, Church was right!

Church seemed to think that his system could escape Gödels limitations (we now know this is impossible). And Kleene actually agreed? Whats going on?

Oh, Kleenes next sentence explains the reason:

In his system there is a proof of its own consistency, since in fact it is inconsistent (so all its sentences are provable), as Church had thought possible (1933 top p. 842) and as Rosser and I showed later (Kleene and Rosser 1935).

Kleene, is this how you joke about your teachers system? This has a bit of a hell joke flavor. Yes, Churchs system did indeed surpass Gödels limitations, because it is inconsistent!

The so-called inconsistency means that this system TT can prove a proposition PP, and at the same time it can prove ¬P\neg P. This is already bad intuitively: this system has some kind of contradiction. Technically its even worse, because it means that this system can prove any proposition. Suppose we have TPT \vdash P and T¬PT \vdash \neg P, to prove an arbitrary proposition QQ, we can make the following derivation:

  1. PP
  2. PQP \lor Q
  3. ¬P\neg P
  4. QQ

The reasoning rules used in this derivation are the introduction and elimination of or, almost any formal system has this rule. So, if a system is inconsistent, then it can prove any proposition. Generally, we think such a system is meaningless.

Kleene and another student of Church, Rosser, proved in 1935 that Churchs system was inconsistent. Their proof is called the Kleene-Rosser paradox. This paradox is technically complex, but intuitively, Churchs system can already encode any computable function, which strongly implies inconsistency.

In a 1984 article written by Rosser, he also introduced how to use the technique invented by Curry to prove the inconsistency of Churchs system, which is a simple proof.

In fact, in the same-named (and 1932 same-named) paper published by Church in 1933, he found that his system was inconsistent. To resolve this inconsistency, he deleted axiom 19 and added two axioms, bringing the total number of axioms to 38. He thought this new system was consistent, but we now know that this system is also inconsistent.

So, in short, because Churchs system was inconsistent and extremely complex, it was forgotten.

Conclusion

Churchs initial goal was to formalize mathematics with his system, but this system is now long forgotten; and a by-product of his system, λ\lambda calculus, has become the cornerstone of computer science. These great names, Church, Kleene, Turing, Gödel, …, are forever in the history of computer science.

Their work, in general, should still be called recursion theory. Especially many of Kleenes studies are studying the relationship between uncomputable sets and their relationships. However, I still feel that if a subject called computational theory does not talk about λ\lambda calculus, recursive functions, but talks about automata, it really lacks a lot of interesting things. If your computational theory is also a bunch of automata, I hope this article can make you interested in λ\lambda calculus.

Quiz

  1. Church numbers were first published in Churchs 1933 paper, which also gave the expression of Peanos axioms in his system. However, whether it is his expressed Church numbers or Peanos axioms, they all start from 11, not from 00. Can you think about why Church didnt put 00 in his system? This is not just his taste, but more of a technical issue.
  2. In modern λ\lambda calculus, we generally define the constructor of (binary) tuples as
    (a,b)λaλbλf.fab(a, b) \equiv \lambda a \lambda b \lambda f. f a b
    fst and snd are defined as
    fstλp.p(λaλb.a)sndλp.p(λaλb.b) \begin{aligned} \text{fst} &\equiv \lambda p. p (\lambda a \lambda b. a) \\ \text{snd} &\equiv \lambda p. p (\lambda a \lambda b. b) \end{aligned}
    The definition of tuples is an important step in Kleenes definition of the predecessor function, but can Kleene define tuples like this? Why? If not, can you give a definition of tuples that Kleene can use? (Hint: See [Kleene 1981] for the answer)
  3. If it is said that Churchs original system is inconsistent, then why is λ\lambda calculus itself not affected by this problem? Wouldnt anyone think that λ\lambda calculus would also be inconsistent?

Further Reading

  1. Kleene, S. C. (1981). Origins of recursive function theory. Annals of the History of Computing, 3(1), 52-67.
  2. Church, A. (1933). A set of postulates for the foundation of logic. Annals of Mathematics, 34(4), 839-864.
  3. Church A. (1936). An unsolvable problem of elementary number theory. American Journal of Mathematics, 58(2), 345-363.
  4. Church A. (1941). The Calculi of Lambda-Conversion. Princeton University Press.
  5. Church A. (1932). A set of postulates for the foundation of logic. Annals of Mathematics, 33(2), 346-366.
  6. Rosser J. B. (1984). Highlights of the history of the lambda calculus. Annals of the History of Computing, 6(4), 337-349.

Appendix: Churchs 37 Axioms

Thanks to deep learning technology, I was able to simply extract the latex code of Churchs 37 axioms.

  1. Σ(φ)φΠ(φ,φ)\boldsymbol{\Sigma}(\varphi) \supset_{\varphi} \Pi(\varphi, \varphi).
  2. x. φ(x)φ. Π(φ,ψ)ψψ(x)x . \ \varphi(x) \supset_{\varphi} . \ \Pi(\varphi, \psi) \supset_\psi \psi(x).
  3. Σ(σ)σ. [σ(x)xφ(x)]p. Π(φ,ψ)ψ. σ(x)xψ(x)\mathbf{\Sigma}(\sigma) \supset_\sigma . \ \left[\sigma(x) \supset_x \varphi(x)\right] \supset_p . \ \Pi(\varphi, \psi) \supset_\psi . \ \sigma(x) \supset_x \psi(x).
  4. Σ(ϱ)ϱ.Σy[ϱ(x)xφ(x,y)]p. [ϱ(x)xΠ(φ(x),ψ(x))]ψ\mathbf{\Sigma}(\varrho) \supset_{\varrho} . \Sigma y\left[\varrho(x) \supset_x \varphi(x, y)\right] \supset_p . \ \left[\varrho(x) \supset_x \Pi(\varphi(x), \psi(x))\right] \supset_\psi. [ϱ(x)xφ(x,y)]y. ϱ(x)xψ(x,y)\left[\varrho(x) \supset_x \varphi(x, y)\right] \supset_y . \ \varrho(x) \supset_x \psi(x, y).
  5. Σ(ς)φ. Π(φ,ψ)ψ. φ(f(x))fxψ(f(x))\Sigma(\varsigma) \supset_{\varphi} . \ \Pi(\varphi, \psi) \supset_\psi . \ \varphi(f(x)) \supset_{f x} \psi(f(x)).
  6. x. φ(x)p. Π(ς,ψ(x))ψψ(x,x)x . \ \varphi(x) \supset_p . \ \Pi(\varsigma, \psi(x)) \supset_\psi \psi(x, x).
  7. φ(x,f(x))qfx. Π(φ(x),ψ(x))ψψ(x,f(x))\varphi(x, f(x)) \supset_{q f x} . \ \Pi(\varphi(x), \psi(x)) \supset_\psi \psi(x, f(x)).
  8. Σ(ϱ)ϱ.Σy[ϱ(x)xφ(x,y)]p. [ϱ(x)xΠ(φ(x),ψ)]ψ\mathbf{\Sigma}(\varrho) \supset_{\varrho} . \Sigma y\left[\varrho(x) \supset_x \varphi(x, y)\right] \supset_p . \ \left[\varrho(x) \supset_x \Pi(\varphi(x), \psi)\right] \supset_\psi. [ϱ(x)xφ(x,y)]yψ(y)\left[\varrho(x) \supset_x \varphi(x, y)\right] \supset_y \psi(y).
  9. x. φ(x)φΣ(φ)x . \ \varphi(x) \supset_{\varphi} \Sigma(\varphi).
  10. Σxφ(f(x))fφΣ(φ)\Sigma x \varphi(f(x)) \supset_{f \varphi} \Sigma(\varphi).
  11. φ(x,x)φxΣ(φ(x))\varphi(x, x) \supset_{\varphi x} \Sigma(\varphi(x)).
  12. Σ(φ)φΣxφ(x)\Sigma(\varphi) \supset_{\varphi} \Sigma x \varphi(x).
  13. Σ(φ)φ. [φ(x)xψ(x)]ψΠ(φ,ψ)\Sigma(\varphi) \supset_{\varphi} . \ \left[\varphi(x) \supset_x \psi(x)\right] \supset_\psi \boldsymbol{\Pi}(\varphi, \psi).
  14. pp. qqpqp \supset_p . \ q \supset_q p q.
  15. pqqppp q \supset_{q p} p.
  16. pqpqqp q \supset_{p q} q.
  17. ΣxΣθ[φ(x). θ(x). Π(ψ,θ)]pψΠ(φ,ψ)\Sigma x \Sigma \theta[\varphi(x) . \ \sim \theta(x) . \ \Pi(\psi, \theta)] \supset_{p \psi} \sim \Pi(\varphi, \psi).
  18. Π(φ,ψ)φψΣxΣθ. φ(x). θ(x). Π(ψ,θ)\sim \Pi(\varphi, \psi) \supset_{\varphi \psi} \Sigma x \Sigma \theta . \ \varphi(x) . \ \sim \theta(x) . \ \Pi(\psi, \theta).
  19. ΣxΣθ[φ(u,x).θ(u).Σ(φ(y))yθ(y)]φuΣ(φ(u))\Sigma x \Sigma \theta\left[\sim \varphi(u, x) . \sim \theta(u) . \Sigma(\varphi(y)) \supset_y \theta(y)\right] \supset_{\varphi u} \sim \Sigma(\varphi(u)).
  20. Σ(φ)φΣxφ(x)\sim \boldsymbol{\Sigma}(\varphi) \supset_{\varphi} \boldsymbol{\Sigma} x \sim \varphi(x).
  21. ppqqpqp \supset_p \sim q \supset_q \sim p q.
  22. pp. qq. pq\sim p \supset_p . \ q \supset_q \sim . \ p q.
  23. ppqqpq\sim p \supset_p \sim q \supset_q \sim p q.
  24. pp. [. pq]qqp \supset_p . \ [\sim . \ p q] \supset_q \sim q.
  25. [.φ(u). ψ(u)]φψu. [[[φ(x). ψ(x)]xϱ(x)][\sim . \varphi(u) . \ \psi(u)] \supset_{\varphi \psi u} . \ \left[\left[[\varphi(x) . \ \sim \psi(x)] \supset_x \varrho(x)\right]\right.. [[φ(x). ψ(x)]xϱ(x)]. [φ(x). ψ(x)]xϱ(x)]ϱϱ(u)\left.\left[[\sim \varphi(x) . \ \psi(x)] \supset_x \varrho(x)\right] . \ [\sim \varphi(x) . \ \sim \psi(x)] \supset_x \varrho(x)\right] \supset_{\varrho} \varrho(u).
  26. pppp \supset_p \sim \sim p.
  27. ppp\sim \sim p \supset_p p.
  28. Σ(φ)φ. Σ(ψ)ψΠ(φ,ψ)\sim \Sigma(\varphi) \supset_{\varphi} . \ \Sigma(\psi) \supset_\psi \Pi(\varphi, \psi).
  29. Σ(φ)φΣ(ψ)ψΠ(φ,ψ)\sim \boldsymbol{\Sigma}(\varphi) \supset_{\varphi} \sim \boldsymbol{\Sigma}(\psi) \supset_\psi \boldsymbol{\Pi}(\varphi, \psi).
  30. x. φ(x)φ. [θ(x). ψ(x)ψΠ(θ,ψ)]θφ(ι(θ))x . \ \varphi(x) \supset_{\varphi} . \ \left[\theta(x) . \ \psi(x) \supset_\psi \Pi(\theta, \psi)\right] \supset_\theta \varphi(\iota(\theta)).
  31. φ(ι(θ))θφΠ(θ,φ)\varphi(\iota(\theta)) \supset_{\theta \varphi} \boldsymbol{\Pi}(\theta, \varphi).
  32. E(ι(θ))θΣ(θ)E(\iota(\theta)) \supset_\theta \Sigma(\theta).
  33. [φ(x,y)xy. φ(y,z)zφ(x,z)][φ(x,y)xyφ(y,x)]φ. φ(u,v)uv\left[\varphi(x, y) \supset_{x y} . \ \varphi(y, z) \supset_z \varphi(x, z)\right]\left[\varphi(x, y) \supset_{x y} \varphi(y, x)\right] \supset_{\varphi} . \ \varphi(u, v) \supset_{u v}. ψ(A(φ,u))ψψ(A(φ,v))\psi(A(\varphi, u)) \supset_\psi \psi(A(\varphi, v)).
  34. [φ(x,y)xy. φ(y,z)zφ(x,z)][φ(x,y)xyφ(y,x)]φ\left[\varphi(x, y) \supset_{x y} . \ \varphi(y, z) \supset_z \varphi(x, z)\right]\left[\varphi(x, y) \supset_{x y} \varphi(y, x)\right] \supset_{\varphi}. [φ(x,y)xyθ(x,y)]θθ(u,v)uv.ψ(A(φ,u))ψψ(A(φ,v))\left[\varphi(x, y) \supset_{x y} \theta(x, y)\right] \supset_\theta \sim \theta(u, v) \supset_{u v} \sim . \psi(A(\varphi, u)) \supset_\psi \psi(A(\varphi, v)).
  35. [ψ(A(φ,u))ψψ(A(φ,v))]φuvφ(u,v)\left[\psi(A(\varphi, u)) \supset_\psi \psi(A(\varphi, v))\right] \supset_{\varphi u v} \varphi(u, v).
  36. E(A(φ))φ. φ(x,y)xy. φ(y,z)zφ(x,z)E(A(\varphi)) \supset_{\varphi} . \ \varphi(x, y) \supset_{x y} . \ \varphi(y, z) \supset_z \varphi(x, z).
  37. E(A(φ))φφ(x,y)xyφ(y,x)E(A(\varphi)) \supset_{\varphi} \varphi(x, y) \supset_{x y} \varphi(y, x).